domingo, 8 de septiembre de 2019

BioEdge: In defence of conscientious objection

BioEdge: In defence of conscientious objection

Bioedge

In defence of conscientious objection
    
Photo by Hush Naidoo on Unsplash
Over the last few years there has been a vigorous and fascinating debate about the use of conscientious objection (CO) in healthcare. CO is when doctors (and other healthcare professionals) opt-out of providing a medical service because they have serious moral objections—abortion is a widely cited example.
If enough doctors object to abortions, there is a legitimate concern that some patients will have difficulty accessing them—for example in Italy 70% of obstetricians refuse to participate in abortions, even though this isn’t the intention of CO. Some ethicists have argued there is no place for CO at all in healthcare, in the strongest of terms.
Curiously, though—and this is what aroused our interest—these same ethicists usually recognise that there are still some instances when doctors should be permitted to object and withhold their services. But how can they allow some objections and not others? One way is by claiming these objections aren’t really cases of CO, which seems a bit arbitrary. A better approach is to propose sensible criteria for allowing certain objections and disallowing others, and this is where the CO debate is at the moment.
Part of this debate involves critiquing certain features of common COs such as abortion, and our recent paper in the Journal of Medical Ethics examines two major criticisms.
The first is that CO may deny patients a beneficial medical procedure, and this is a bad outcome. However, we examined the research, and concluded that abortion is of dubious medical benefit—a somewhat controversial judgment given it is so widely used. Most abortions are requested for social reasons, not medical reasons, and so we believe this criticism isn’t valid.
The second criticism we tackle is that CO is based on personal beliefs, and these are untestable.
Yes, we agree that most moral beliefs are untestable, whether they are religiously based or not. Science can provide us with empirical evidence to inform our moral beliefs, but it can’t tell us whether abortion is right or wrong. The problem for critics of CO is that personal beliefs aren’t easy to replace with some other criteria if you still want to allow some objections. For example, if you instead use the ‘values of the profession’, it turns out that these are still partly predicated on personal beliefs regarding what’s good and what’s harmful for patients—and the more controversial the case, the less useful professional values turn out to be.
A suggested alternative is the ‘scope of professional practice’. Surely this takes personal beliefs out of the picture!
But there’s still a problem—sooner or later there will be something that is legal and within the scope of practice that doctors believe is harmful to patients in some way. One example is the practice of nontherapeutic infant male circumcision. Some ethicists claim doctors should just comply anyway—but we would prefer doctors who believe a treatment to be harmful and/or of no clear benefit to say so, and refuse to provide it!
After disarming these criticisms, we make our own proposal of a standard for what COs should be permitted that we think is worth considering: doctors should be able to object to providing any treatment or procedure that is not clinically indicated. A clinically indicated procedure is one that will clearly benefit a patient’s health and is appropriate for the condition being treated. We don’t think it fair that doctors should have to sacrifice their moral integrity for procedures that are not clinically indicated, even if they are part of their scope of practice.
Our suggestion is unlikely to cover all cases that we think doctors should be able to CO to, but it seems to be a reasonable starting point. There are certainly no easy answers when it comes to how CO should be implemented, but we hope our paper has clarified some issues and moved the conversation forward.
Bruce Philip Blackshaw is a doctoral research in philosophy at the University of Birmingham. Daniel Rodger is a Lecturer in Perioperative Practice at London South Bank University. This article has been republished from the blog of the Journal of Medical Ethics under a CC-BY-NC licence.
Bioedge

Below is an article about a 73-year-old Indian woman who has just given birth to twin boys. This is a story which used to fly onto the front page, but is now a bit ho-hum. To stir media interest, we need to break through the next barrier. “Centenarian gives birth to twins, say Indian doctors” – now that would be newsworthy, I think. At least the first centenarian would.

The ho-hum factor may account for the fact that few questions were raised about obvious ethical issues involved in septuagenarians giving birth.

First of all, it is obviously reinforcing a sexist stereotype – that a woman is useless unless she has children. Furthermore, despite reassuring words from the doctors, it is a serious risk to the mother’s health.

Second, the children of a 73-year-old mother will soon be orphans. In fact, their father had a stroke on the day after they were born. No one seems to be thinking about their welfare and their future. They are just status symbols for their parents and the doctors.

Why did the doctors cooperate? For the money? For the fame? It strikes me as completely unethical.



m.png
Michael Cook
Editor
BioEdge
 Comment on BioedgeFind Us on FacebookFollow us on Twitter
NEWS THIS WEEK

by Michael Cook | Sep 07, 2019
Conflict set up between freedom of speech and freedom of religion

by Michael Cook | Sep 07, 2019
Their brain waves resemble pre-term babies

by Michael Cook | Sep 07, 2019
“The happiest time of my life,” says her husband

by Michael Cook | Sep 07, 2019
Child born healthy

by Michael Cook | Sep 07, 2019
Bernie Sanders stirs up a hornets’ nest

by Michael Cook | Sep 07, 2019
A parable of media hype

by Michael Cook | Sep 07, 2019
Is it realistic?
IN DEPTH THIS WEEK

by Bruce P. Blackshaw and Daniel Rodger | Sep 08, 2019
​​​​​​​Why not make clinically indicated procedures the benchmark?
Bioedge

BioEdge
Level 1, 488 Botany Road, Alexandria NSW 2015 Australia
Phone: +61 2 8005 8605
Mobile: 0422-691-615

No hay comentarios: