Conscientious objection: how much discretionary power should physicians have?
by Xavier Symons | 25 Aug 2019 |
There has been significant debate about conscientious objection in healthcare in recent years. Some scholars have argued that conscience protections in law and professional codes of conduct may lead to negligence in medical care and may put patient wellbeing at risk. For example, Oxford bioethicist Julian Savulescu has argued that conscience protections open a “Pandora's box of idiosyncratic, bigoted, discriminatory medicine”, and that “public servants must act in the public interest, not their own”.
But should physicians have the right to exercise professional discretion with patients?
Some scholars, such as Daniel Sulmasy, argue that physician discretion is an essential part of good medical practice, and that restrictions on conscientious objection would have a negative impact on medical care. In a 2017 article in the Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, Sulmasy argued that physicians should have the right to exercise their judgement about which treatments they will provide, provided that they are not practicing medicine in a manner that is discriminatory or harmful to patients. He wrote that “professional judgments are both technical and moral in all cases” and that it is important to “respect and protect a wide discretionary space for physicians regarding ethically controversial interventions”. According to Sulmasy,
“Conscientious refraining from actions when such restraint does not risk illness, injury, or death, would not seem to rise to the level of being sufficient grounds for compelling conscience”.
This argument, however, has been criticised. Doug McConnell, an ethicist at the University of Oxford, argues in the journal Bioethics (and in Oxford's Practical Ethics blog) that too much physician discretion can lead to people being denied basic forms of medical care. While Sulmasy agrees that physicians should not practice discriminatory medicine, his framework still allows for objecting doctors to refuse patients treatment for “commonly accepted ailments, such as rashes, headaches, mild depression and anxiety”.
McConnell also argues that Sulmasy’s framework undermines the fiduciary relationship that clinicians should have with their patients. Sulmasy appears to give equal weight to the interests of doctors and the interests of patients. Thus, a doctor can refuse a patient a treatment if the treatment conflicts with their ethical or religious convictions. But McConnell argues that this is incompatible with a fiduciary relationship:
“within fiduciary relationships, the party with the fiduciary duty should place greater weight on the others’ interests and, so be prepared to go against his conscience”.
Physicians, in other words, should be prepared to put patient interests ahead of their own moral or religious convictions.
Yet McConnell may have misunderstood Sulmasy’s account of the fiduciary relationship between clinicians and patients. Sulmasy is a student of Edmund Pellegrino -- a medical ethicist who wrote at length about the notion of “the patient’s good”, and argued that this should be at the centre of a doctor’s professional concerns. It is hard to believe that Sulmasy would downplay a physician’s duties to their patients.
Perhaps the real distinction between McConnell and Sulmasy is not their concern for the good of the patient, but rather the way in which they conceptualise the patient’s good. For Sulmasy, the patient’s good is determined by a set of moral and technical considerations, whereas for McConnell, the patient’s good is more a matter of their individual preferences and interests.
Xavier Symons is deputy editor of BioEdge
Sorry, guys, late again. There's a good variety of topics below -- we'd love to get your comments.
Michael Cook Editor BioEdge |
NEWS THIS WEEK
by Michael Cook | Aug 25, 2019
What happens when private interests trump public necessity?by Michael Cook | Aug 25, 2019
Some have been using their own sperm to get clients pregnantby Michael Cook | Aug 25, 2019
A wife’s devotion pays off by Michael Cook | Aug 25, 2019
If it works in mice, it could also work with humansby Nic Zumaran | Aug 25, 2019
The risks for a child-to-be are not outweighed by direct benefitsby Xavier Symons | Aug 25, 2019
And how should we understand the idea of 'the patient's good'?by Xavier Symons | Aug 24, 2019
Children are being abandoned by their commissioning parentsIN DEPTH THIS WEEK
by Patrick Foong | Aug 25, 2019
Amazingly, recent experiments fall between regulatory stools in Australiaby Anna Almendrala | Aug 24, 2019
Some argue that compulsory information pamphlets might make victims feel responsible for abuseBioEdge
Level 1, 488 Botany Road, Alexandria NSW 2015 Australia
Phone: +61 2 8005 8605
Mobile: 0422-691-615
No hay comentarios:
Publicar un comentario